next up previous
Next: Proving Statements About Recursive Up: Towards a Mathematical Science Previous: How Can A Mathematical

Using Conditional Expressions to Define Functions Recursively

In ordinary mathematical language, there are certain tools for defining new functions in terms of old ones. These tools are composition and the identification of variables. As it happens, these tools are inadequate computable in terms of old ones. It is then customary to define all functions that can reasonably be regarded as to give a verbal definition. For example, the function |x| is usually defined in words.

If we add a single formal tool, namely conditional expressions to our mathematical notation, and if we allow conditional expressions to be used recursively in a manner that I shall describe, we can define, in a completely formal way, all functions that can reasonably be regarded as computable in terms of an initial set. We will use the ALGOL 60 notation for conditional expressions in this paper.

We shall use conditional expressions in the simple form

displaymath409

where p is a propositional expression whose value is true or false. The value of the conditional expression is a if p has the value true and b if p has the value false. When conditional expressions are used, the stock of predicates one has available for constructing p's is just as important as the stock of ordinary functions to be used in forming the a's and b's by composition. The following are examples of functions defined by conditional expressions:

  1. tex2html_wrap_inline431
  2. tex2html_wrap_inline433
  3. n! = g(n, 1)
    where
    tex2html_wrap_inline437
  4. n!=f(n,0,1)
    where
    tex2html_wrap_inline441
  5. tex2html_wrap_inline443
    where
    tex2html_wrap_inline445
  6. tex2html_wrap_inline447

The first of these is the only non-recursive definition in the group. Next, we have three different procedures for computing n!; they can be shown to be equivalent by the methods to be described in this paper. Then we define the predecessor function tex2html_wrap_inline451 for positive integers tex2html_wrap_inline453 in terms of the successor function tex2html_wrap_inline455 Finally, we define addition in terms of the successor, the predecessor and equality. In all of the definitions, except for the first, the domain of the variables is taken to be the set of non-negative integers.

As an example of the use of these definitions, we shall show how to compute 2! by the second definition of n!. We have

displaymath63

Note that if we attempted to compute n! for any n but a non-negative integer the successive reductions would not terminate. In such cases we say that the computation does not converge. Some recursive functions converge for all values of their arguments, some converge for some values of the arguments, and some never converge. Functions that always converge are called total functions, and the others are called partial functions. One of the earliest major results of recursive function theory is that there is no formalism that gives all the computable total functions and no partial functions.

We have proved [McC63] that the above method of defining computable functions, starting from just the successor function tex2html_wrap_inline463 and equality, yields all the computable functions of integers. This leads us to assert that we have the complete set of tools for defining functions which are computable in terms of given base functions.

If we examine the next to last line of our computation of 2! we see that we cannot simply regard the conditional expression

displaymath409

as a function of the three quantities p, a, and b. If we did so, we would be obliged to compute g(-1, 0) before evaluating the conditional expression, and this computation would not converge. What must happen is that when p is true we take a as the value of the conditional expression without even looking at b.

Any reference to recursive functions in the rest of this paper refers to functions defined by the above methods.


next up previous
Next: Proving Statements About Recursive Up: Towards a Mathematical Science Previous: How Can A Mathematical

John McCarthy
Tue May 14 13:32:03 PDT 1996